Thought experiments are quite common in philosophy, but they are also quite problematic. Some thought experiments are meant to be taken almost literally (as in the case of Hobbes’s state of nature), while other are meant to lead the reader to a ‘logical’ conclusion based on a number of propositions (as in the case of Searle’s Chinese Room). Whatever the intention of the philosophers may be, it is important to establish what kinds of thought experiments there are, unless we fall prey to the common misconception that they are entirely nonsensical. Understanding the kinds of thought experiments would hopefully help with understanding the role they play in particular philosopher’s work. The general disagreement regarding thought experiments is that they are simply not empirically verifiable.1 As I will show below, not all thought experiments require verification.
There are in general terms three kinds of thought experiments:
First, there are thought experiments that rely on sound theories without any intention of experiments. If the theory is sound, then the conclusion would follow. Good examples of such thought experiments are abundant in physics, where a physicist did not need to do the actual experiment; doing the thought experiment sufficed. Most of us are familiar with Einstein’s thought experiment regarding relativity.2 Others may remember that Einstein did not need proof of light bending through photographs by Eddington in 1919, famously saying that were the proof to fail, “The theory is correct anyway”. Such thought experiments are also possible in philosophy, of course, though they usually yield less fascinating pictures. The point here is rather simple. The first kind of thought experiments can be replicated as actual experiments. There is not always a need for verification of the thought experiment, but one could certainly do the experiment. In physics this is perhaps easier (to a degree) than in philosophy, but the point remains that as long as the theory is sound, verification is possible though not necessary.
Other thought experiments rely on sound theoretical framework, but are impossible to replicate. They are conceivable in thought, but they are impossible as an actual experiment (yet).3 This type of thought experiments require a level of concreteness that can be backed up by data, without the experiment itself being replicable. I have mentioned Searle’s Chinese Room4 before, which falls under this category – while it is practically impossible to fill a room with all the possible objects, the thought experiment has a sound theoretical framework that allows for a conclusion to be drawn. So in short, the second kind of thought experiments cannot be replicated as actual experiments and thus cannot be verified, but are nonetheless sensible. In physics, we cannot build a model universe, but a lot of our theories derive from a particular theoretical understanding of the universe; and in case of philosophy there are, for instance, ethical problems which do not allow for actual experimentation (the infamous trolley problem comes to mind).
The third kind of thought experiments is why thought experiments have such a bad reputation. They lack the theoretical framework and are (rather obviously) not replicable. If taken literally, they are quite absurd: one is asked to picture some ridiculous scenario (surreal even for Hollywood standards) and to apply our common sense in trying to envisage how we would feel about such a case – i.e. to draw conclusions from that scenario, based on our intuitions that are reliant on the lack of absurdity. We can discern two features from this kind of thought experiments:
1.The hypothesis relies on a situation which is beyond the sense data (sidenote: I don’t really like this notion of sense data, but it will do) – it is almost impossible to imagine such a situation without giving ourselves inhuman capabilities.
2.The conclusion drawn relies on our common sense or intuition of the impossible.
The problem, as one can imagine, is precisely in the ability to draw an intuitive conclusion on the basis of impossible situations – that is, the lack of sense data is meant to somehow lead to a sensible conclusion. To put this differently, the premise upon which the thought experiment is based (no senses) is contradictory to the type of conclusion that is sought (intuition or common sense). Is it surprising that such thought experiments are difficult to grasp, especially if taken in isolation from the particular text or philosopher in question?5
This brief schema of two features is surpassingly telling of the structure of the thought experiments. While the scenario is grandiose and unimaginable, the conclusion is obvious (and often dull).6 The problem with this kind of thought experiments is precisely the obtuse conclusions that are drawn. Of themselves, the unimaginable situations are quite fascinating and make for great insights longer down the line. The jumping to conclusions prematurely make for a very bad philosophical work, which not only lead to absurdities, but also detract serious philosophical work (and funding is misplaced, discipline shamed, etc.).
In conclusion, in identifying thought experiments, one should ask to what extent the two features are present. Are the premises within the scope of actual experimentation? If not, are the conclusions drawn reliant on the premises? If the latter is a ‘no’ as well, the thought experiment is in all likelihood nonsense intended to persuade you in favour of a particular position.
I think if I were somehow trapped in a time reversal and forced to relive my "educational" years, one of the least welcome experiences would be having to write an essay in response to a test question about some particular aspect of philosophy or what is distinctive about some particular philosopher and her (ha... some feigned PC going on here) writings.
I think I was almost always feeling that I had been enveloped in a dense and obscuring "mental fog" whenever the curriculum was on the subject of philosophy.
It all seemed like "Much Ado About Nothing", if my current memories of how I felt about it at the time are accurate.